Provenance in Databases: Why, How, and Where

Chapter 1: Introduction

Data provenance, also known as data lineage, describes the origin and history of data as it is moved, copied, transformed, and queried in a data system. In the context of relational databases, provenance will allow us to point at a tuple (or part of a tuple) in the output of a query and ask why or how it got there. In this book, we'll study three forms of provenance known as why-provenance, how-provenance, and where-provenance.

Lineage

The lineage of tuple $t$ in the output of evaluating query $Q$ against database instance $I$ is a subset of the tuples in $I$ (known as a witness) that are sufficient for $t$ to appear in the output. Lineage is best explained through an example. Consider the following relations $R$

id A
$t_1$ 1
$t_2$ 2

and $S$

id A B
$t_3$ 1 blue
$t_4$ 1 blue
$t_5$ 1 red
$t_6$ 2 blue
$t_7$ 2 red

and consider the query $Q$:

SELECT R.A
FROM   R, S
WHERE  R.A = S.A AND S.B = blue

The result of evaluating query $Q$ is:

id A
$t_8$ 1
$t_9$ 2

The lineage of $t_8$ is $\set{t_1, t_3, t_4}$, and the lineage of $t_9$ is $\set{R(t_2), S(t_6)}$. While the lineage of a tuple $t$ is sufficient for $t$ to appear in the output, the lineage is not necessary. For example, the lineage of $t_8$ does not capture the fact that $t_3$ and $t_4$ do not both have to appear in the input for $t_8$ to appear in the output. In fact, for a given output tuple $t$ there could be an exponential number of sufficient (but not necessary) witnesses for it.

Why-Provenance

Why-provenance is similar to lineage but tries to avoid considering an exponential number of potential witnesses. Instead, it focuses on a restricted set of witnesses known as the witness basis. For example, the witness basis of $t_8$ is $\set{\set{t_1, t_3}, \set{t1_, t_4}}$. A minimal witness basis is a witness basis consisting only of minimal witnesses. That is, it won't include two witnesses $w$ and $w'$ where $w \subseteq w'$. The witness basis of two equivalent queries might differ, but the two queries are guaranteed to share the same minimal witness basis.

How-Provenance

Given an output tuple $t$, why-provenance provides witnesses that prove $t$ should appear in the output. However, why-provenance does not tell us how $t$ was formed from a witness. How-provenance uses a provenance semiring to hint at how an tuple was derived. The semiring consists of polynomials over tuple ids. The polynomial $t^2 + t \cdot t'$ hints at two derivations: one which uses $t$ twice and one which uses $t$ and $t'$.

Where-Provenance

Where-provenance is very similar to why-provenance except that we'll now point at a particular entry (or location) of an output tuple $t$ and ask which input locations it was copied from. For example, the where-provenance of the $A$ entry of tuple $t_8$ is the $A$ entry of tuple $t_3$ or $t_4$.

Eager vs Lazy

There are two main ways to implement data lineage:

  1. an eager (or bookkeeping or annotating) approach, and
  2. a lazy (or non-annotating) approach.

In the eager approach, tuples are annotated and their annotations are propagated through the evaluation of a query. The lineage of an output tuple can then be directly determined using its annotations. In the lazy approach, tuples are not annotated. Instead, the lineage of a tuple must be derived by inspecting the query and input database.

Notational Preliminaries

Finally, this is the syntax of monotone relation algebra:

$$
\begin{array}{rrl}
  Q & ::= & R \\
    & |   & \set{t} \\
    & |   & \sigma_{\theta}(Q) \\
    & |   & \pi_{U}(Q) \\
    & |   & Q_1 \bowtie Q_2 \\
    & |   & Q_1 \cup Q_2 \\
    & |   & \rho_{A \mapsto B}(Q) \\
\end{array}
$$

This is the semantics:

$$
\begin{array}{rrl}
  \denote{R}(I) & = &
    \set{t} \\
  \denote{\set{t}}(I) & = &
    I(R) \\
  \denote{\sigma_{\theta}(Q)}(I) & = &
    \setst{t \in \denote{Q}(I)}{\theta(t)} \\
  \denote{\pi_{U}(Q)}(I) & = &
    \setst{t[U]}{t \in \denote{Q}(I)} \\
  \denote{Q_1 \bowtie Q_2}(I) & = &
    \setst{t}{t[U_1] \in \denote{Q_1}(I), t[U_2] \in \denote{Q_2}(I)} \\
  \denote{Q_1 \cup Q_2}(I) & = &
    \denote{Q_1}(I) \cup \denote{Q_2}(I) \\
  \denote{\rho_{A \mapsto B}(Q)}(I) & = &
    \setst{t[A \mapsto B]}{t \in \denote{Q}(I)} \\
\end{array}
$$

Often, we will omit the denotational brackets $\denote{\cdot}$ and abbreviate $\denote{Q}(I)$ as $Q(I)$. We will also sometimes denote a grouping by columns $G$ as $\alpha_G(Q)$.

Chapter 2: Why-Provenance

Lineage

First, we review lineage. Let $Op$ be a relation operator over input relations $(\Rs)$. The lineage of a tuple $t \in Op(\Rs)$ is a subset $(\Rprimes)$ of $(\Rs)$ such that:

  1. $Op(\Rprimes) = \set{t}$;
  2. For all $i \in [n]$ and for all $t_i \in R_i'$, $Op(R_1', \ldots, \set{t_i}, \ldots, R_n') \neq \emptyset$; and
  3. $(\Rprimes)$ is maximal among subsets satisfying 1 and 2.

1 ensures the lineage is relevant to $t$, 2 ensures that no irrelevant tuples are included, and 3 ensures the lineage is "complete". Given the definition of lineage, we can compute it. Let $\lineage(t, Op(\Rs))$ be the lineage of tuple $t \in Op(\Rs)$.

$$
\begin{align*}
  \lineage(t, \select{\theta}(R))
    &= (\set{t}) \\
  \lineage(t, \project{U}(R))
    &= (\setst{t' \in R}{t'[U] = t}) \\
  \lineage(t, R_1 \join \cdots \join R_n)
    &= \left.(\setst{t_i \in R_i}{t[U_i] = t_i})\right\vert_{i \in [n]} \\
  \lineage(t, R_1 \cup \cdots \cup R_n)
    &= \left.(\setst{t_i \in R_i}{t = t_i})\right\vert_{i \in [n]} \\
  \lineage(t, R_1 \setdiff R_2)
    &= (\set{t}, R_2) \\
  \lineage(t, \alpha_G(R))
    &= (\setst{t' \in R}{t[G] = t'[G]})
\end{align*}
$$

Next, consider a query $Op(\Qs)$ run on a database $I$. Let $S_i = Q_i(I)$ and let $\lineage(t, Op(\Qs), I)$ be the lineage of $t$ in $Op(\Qs)(I)$.

$$
\lineage(t, Op(\Qs), I) =
  \bigcup_{S_i(t') \in \lineage(t, Op(\Ss))} \lineage(S_i(t'), S_i)
$$

Consider again the relations $R$ and $S$ and the query $Q$ from above. We can express $Q$ in the relation algebra---$Q = \project{A}(\select{S.B = \text{blue}}(R \join S))$---and compute the lineage of $t_8$.

$$
\begin{align*}
  \lineage(t_8, \project{A}(\select{S.a=\blue}(R(I) \join S(I))))
    &= \set{(1, blue)} \\
  \lineage(\set{(1, blue)}, \select{S.a=\blue}(R(I) \join S(I)))
    &= \set{(1, blue)} \\
  \lineage(\set{(1, blue)}, R(I) \join S(I))
    &= \set{\set{t_1}, \set{t_3, t_4}}
\end{align*}
$$

A Compositional Definition of Lineage

The previous definition of lineage has a couple flaws: (a) it's confusing, (b) it doesn't handle queries with constants, and (c) it is only defined for tuples in the output of a query. We can fix these flaws with a compositional definition of lineage. Let $\lin$ be a partial function which takes a query $Q$, a database $I$, and a tuple $t$ and returns

Define the strict union ($\strictunion$),

$$
\begin{aligned}
  \bot \strictunion X &= \bot \\
  X \strictunion \bot &= \bot \\
  X \strictunion Y &= X \cup Y
\end{aligned}
$$

lazy union ($\lazyunion$),

$$
\begin{aligned}
  \bot \lazyunion X &= X \\
  X \lazyunion \bot &= X \\
  X \lazyunion Y &= X \cup Y
\end{aligned}
$$

and lazy flattening ($\lazyflattening$) operators.

$$
  \lazyflattening \set{X_1, \ldots, X_n} = \bot \cup X_1 \cup \cdots \cup X_n
$$

Using these operators, defining lineage is straightforward.

$$
\begin{align*}
  \lin{\set{u}, I, t} &= \begin{cases}
    \emptyset & t = u \\
    \bot      & t \neq u
  \end{cases} \\
  \lin(R, I, t) &= \begin{cases}
    \set{R(t)} & t \in I(R) \\
    \bot       & t \notin I(R)
  \end{cases} \\
  \lin(\select{\theta}(Q), I, t) &= \begin{cases}
    \lin(Q, I, t) & \theta(t) \\
    \bot          & \lnot \theta(t)
  \end{cases} \\
  \lin(\project{U}(Q), I, t)
    &= \lazyflattening \setst{\lin(Q, I, t)}{u \in Q(I), u[U] = t} \\
  \lin(\rename{A}{B}(Q), I, t)
    &= \lin(Q, I, t[B \mapsto A]) \\
  \lin(Q_1 \join Q_2, I, t)
    &= \lin(Q_1, I, t[U_1]) \strictunion \lin(Q_2, I, t[U_2]) \\
  \lin(Q_1 \cup Q_2, I, t)
    &= \lin(Q_1, I, t) \lazyunion \lin(Q_2, I, t)
\end{align*}
$$

It can be shown that this definition of lineage is equivalent to the previous one (ignoring minor representation differences). Moreover, we can capture the correctness of the compositional definition with the following two theorems:

WHIPS

The WHIPS data warehouse system lazily implements lineage for queries with select, project, join, union, set difference, and aggregation. Given a query $Q$, database $I$, and tuple $t \in Q(I)$, WHIPS produces one or more reverse queries which produce the lineage of $t$ when run against $I$.

For simple select-project-join (SPJ) queries---queries that only include the select, project, and join operators---the algorithm produces a single reverse query $Q_r$ for a query $Q$. First, we canonicalize $Q$ into project-select-join form: $\project{A}(\select{\theta}(R_1 \join \cdots \join R_n))$. Then, we form the reverse query $Q_r = \select{\phi}(R_1 \join \cdots \join R_n)$ where $\phi = \theta \land (\land_{A_i \in A} \getfield{R_j}{A_i} = \getfield{t}{A_i})$. After evaluating $Q_r(I)$, a postprocessign step decomposes each tuple into its source tuples from $\Rs$. For example, consider $Q = \project{A}(\select{S.B=\blue}(R \join S))$ from above. Here, $Q_r = \select{S.b=\blue \land \getfield{R}{A} = \getfield{t}{A}}(R \join S)$.

The correctness of this algorithm depends crucially on the fact that lineage is invariant with respect to query rewrites. If this were not true, then the lineage of $Q$ (for some database $I$ and tuple $t$) could be different from the canonicalized $Q$ (for the same database $I$ and tuple $t$). WHIPS makes sure to only support queries for which lineage is invariant to query rewriting, but in general there do exist equivalent queries $Q$ and $Q'$, a database $I$, and a tuple $t$ where $\lin(Q, I, t) \neq \lin(Q', I, t)$. These counterexamples appear when one of $Q$ or $Q'$ include a relation $R$ multiple times. Two counterexamples are given in the book.

To handle arbitrary queries (not just SPJ queries) WHIPS canonicalizes a query $Q$ into a sequence of D-segments and AUSPJ-segments. It then produces a series of queries that correspond to the intermediate results of the query. It then uses the non-compositional definition of lineage to recursively trace lineage through the intermediate results.

Why-Provenance

Recall that lineage is not as precise as it could be. For example, $\lin(Q, I, t_8) = \set{R(t_1), S(t_3), S(t_4)}$, but $\set{R(t_1), S(t_3)}$ and $\set{R(t_1), S(t_4)}$ are both sufficient to produce $t_8$. Why-provenance refines lineage and addresses this problem.

Given a database $I$, query $Q$, and tuple $t$, let $J \subseteq I$ be a witness of $t$ if $t \in Q(J)$. Let $\Wit(Q, I, t) = \setst{J \subseteq I}{t \in Q(J)}$ be the set of all witnesses of $t$ with respect to $Q$ and $I$. A couple things to note:

The why-provenance of a tuple $t$ with respect to a query $Q$ and database $I$--- denoted $\Why(Q, I, t)$---is a subset of $\Wit(Q, I, t)$ known as the witness basis. Each witness in the witness basis is known as a proof-witness. Let $A \Cup B = \setst{a \cup b}{a \in A, b \in B}$.

$$
\begin{align*}
  \Why(\set{u}, I, t) &= \begin{cases}
    \set{\emptyset} & u = t \\
    \emptyset       & u \neq t
  \end{cases} \\
  \Why(R, I, t) &= \begin{cases}
    \set{\set{R(t)}} & t \in R(I) \\
    \emptyset        & t \notin R(I)
  \end{cases} \\
  \Why(\select{\theta}(Q), I, t) &= \begin{cases}
    \Why(Q, I, t) & \theta(t) \\
    \emptyset     & \lnot \theta(t)
  \end{cases} \\
  \Why(\project{A}(Q), I, t)
    &= \bigcup \setst{\Why(Q, I, u)}{u \in Q(I), u[A] = t} \\
  \Why(\rename{A}{B}(Q), I, t)
    &= \Why(Q, I, t[B \mapsto A]) \\
  \Why(Q_1 \join Q_2, I, t)
    &= \Why(Q_1, I, t[A_1]) \Cup \Why(Q_2, I, t[A_2]) \\
  \Why(Q_1 \cup Q_2, I, t)
    &= \Why(Q_1, I, t) \cup \Why(Q_2, I, t)
\end{align*}
$$

Some properties of why-provenance:

Let $(\mathcal{X}, \leq)$ be a partially ordered set. We say $x \in X \subseteq \mathcal{X}$ is minimal if there does not exist a $x' \in X$ where $x' \leq x$. Note that $x$ need not be a minimum element in order to be minimal.

Given a query $Q$, database $I$, and tuple $t$, we say $J \subset I$ is a minimal witness of $t$ if $J$ is a minimal element of $\Wit(Q, I, t)$. Let $\MWit(Q, I, t)$ be the subset of $\Wit(Q, I, t)$ of only minimal witnesses. Similarly, let $\MWhy(Q, I, t)$ be the subset of $\Why(Q, I, t)$ of only minimal witnesses.

Some properties:

Chapter 3: How-Provenance

TODO

Chapter 4: Where-Provenance

TODO

Chapter 5: Comparing Models of Provenance

TODO